Should You Question Everything? | The New Yorker
Every few months, out of curiosity, I red-pill myself. Usually, I start with YouTube. The algorithm is extraordinarily responsive: give a couple of videos a thumbs-up, and your whole feed swerves in a new ideological direction. My political default is center-left, and so the move is to shift it rightward. Thereâs Ben Shapiro debating a bunch of college students; thereâs Charlie Kirk doing the same. Hereâs Elon Musk turning the tables on Don Lemon. A random tough guy is talking to Shawn Ryan about home defense, and a badass mom is excoriating a school board for something or otherâIâm not sure whatâs at stake, but itâs satisfying to watch.
Those are just the quick hits, of course; to get the full effect, you have to move past the merely provocative toward whatâs genuinely interesting. Watch some episodes of âThe Joe Rogan Experience,â but donât skip Lex Fridman and Dwarkesh Patel; subscribe to ReasonTV, and listen to some interviews on âConversations with Tyler.â Find some veterans talking about their experiences during Joe Bidenâs withdrawal from Afghanistan. By this point, your feed will have expanded beyond politics, and red-pilling will have given way to a broad contrarianismâa sense that itâs exciting to rethink your views. People can be contrarian about all sorts of thingsâfitness, money, history, parenting, the meaning of lifeâand not all of it is crazy. You might order some books with which you could profoundly disagree (Patrick J. Deneenâs âRegime Change,â or Abigail Shrierâs âBad Therapyâ) and subscribe to some Substacks. Thereâs a place behind the building where the left and right meet; from there, the country doesnât seem divided so much as scrambled up.
Part of the point of red-pilling yourself is to understand where other people are coming from. Your sister-in-law talks a lot about the depredations of identity politics; your teen-age son is obsessed with how much women take from men during divorce; the guy from the hardware store has put half his savings into crypto, using a strategy based on astrology. Where do they get this stuff? Now you know. Thereâs a diagnostic aspect, too. Just as you go to the doctor once a year to find out if youâre fundamentally healthy, a semi-annual algorithmic derangement can help you learn whether your perspective is as immovable as you take it to be. Are you truly an atheist? Are regulations really a good thing? Could under-policing be the real problem? Your views on all sorts of issues might shift.
But thereâs a twist. The more time you spend having your mind changed online, the more you might sense that thereâs something odd about the way in which opinions tend to be formed and held today. To any question you can ask, thereâs apparently already an answer; in fact, there seem to be more answers than questions. Long before youâve decided what you want to know, youâre told what you should knowâeveryoneâs an insider, or has a theory, or knows the score. A decade ago, it was only journalists who offered âexplainers,â but nowâeven though everybody hates journalistsâeveryoneâs explaining. The Internet pushes us to question everything while foreclosing every question. Itâs a machine for telling you what to think.
âRight now our core political categories are contested,â the New York Times columnist Ross Douthat wrote, last year. There is, he went on, âvigorous disagreementâ about the kind of society we want, with âunstable realignmentsâ holding for only brief periods before collapsing. Whatâs true for politics appears to be true in other areas, too: everything is seemingly up for grabs. In theory, a lack of consensus on so many subjects should mean that we live in a time of widespread intellectual foment, in which we turn over the fundamental questions, exploring them in earnest, searching deeply for durable answers. But is that what weâre doing? Or have we mistaken a simulacrum of thinking for the real thing?
In âOpen Socrates: The Case for a Philosophical Life,â the philosopher Agnes Callard aims to rewind the tape to the beginnings of Western thought, where we can see its mechanisms in vivid relief. âWhat is thinking?â she asks. The Socratic dialoguesâthe few dozen semi-fictional texts in which Socrates is a main character, written in the fourth century B.C. by Plato, Xenophon, and othersâexplored a range of subjects, from the nature of virtue to how we should live with the certainty of death. But they were most important because they modelled a new and powerful way of applying our minds to the questions that matter. What was it?
We speak today of the Socratic methodâthe exploration of ideas through questions and answers. We often imagine the method to be a kind of âsauce,â Callard writes, which we can pour over any intellectual endeavor. Professors love the Socratic method: they enjoy peppering their students with questions, partly to test them, partly to humble them so that theyâre ready to learn. Weâre also generally familiar with a style of contentious discussion in which we try to poke holes in one anotherâs arguments. âWe feel sure that we already are being Socratic,â Callard observes.
Yet if all Socrates had done was pioneer the Q.â&âA., he probably wouldnât have been sentenced to death by his fellow-Athenians. In fact, his intervention was both more radical and more specific. Socrates, Callard argues, inaugurated a whole way of lifeâa new way of being a person. Itâs possible not just to employ the Socratic method, in other words, but to live by it. Doing this entails allowing yourself to be questioned about the basic ideas through which youâve organized your existence. This is an uncomfortable, even painful, process, since, Callard writes, âby the time we have the conceptual wherewithal to wonder about how we should live our lives, weâve long been taking heaps of answers for granted.â Weâre born, we grow up, and before we know it weâve made choices that depend on certain ideas. Believing in valor, we join the military; thirsting for success, we go to law school; drawn to love, we start a family. But whatâs the purpose of valor? What counts as success? What is love? These are what Callard calls âuntimely questions.â Thereâs no good time to ask them; doing that could mess up our lives, because the way we live depends on answers weâve perhaps unreflectingly accepted. But not asking them means living blindly.
The Socratic approach to untimely questions has both intellectual and social dimensions. Intellectually, it involves a kind of pressing yet pure inquiryâa willingness to sit with a question and look at it patiently, rather than search for a way to dismiss it quickly, or turn it into a problem that can be âsolved,â so that you can get on with your life. (Asking âWhat is success?â isnât the same as developing a retirement strategy; asking âWhat is love?â isnât the same as asking, âWhat is my love language?â) The social dimension is perhaps even more challenging. âThe standard approach to thinking privileges what is private and unvoiced and âin the headâ as the core case,â Callard writes, âso that what happens in conversation counts as thinking only insofar as it is an outer echo of an inner event: âthinking out loud.â â But Socratic thinking inverts this picture. Thinking, Callard writes, happens when two people who see themselves as equals pursue a question together. Itâs a chimeric activity, shared but also private and enclosed. My goal, in our shared thought process, isnât to dominate you by scoring points, or to earn the respect of some audience, or to impress you. Itâs to change your mind, or to have my mind changed by youâan outcome that I would find equally satisfying.
Thereâs a big difference between changing your mind for a day and changing it forever. A gulf separates shallow from substantive opinion; strongly felt convictions can have weak foundations, or deep roots. Socratic thinking is a way of braiding together the uncertainty required for growth with the rigor required for endurance. If youâre victorious over me in a debate, I may have no choice but to concede that your arguments are superiorâthough I could still continue to believe that, for reasons I canât articulate, Iâm right. But if we think together, we might arrive at a new and better idea in which we both believe. And if we think together over and over, we might construct a set of shared ideas for how to live.
Weâve all, one hopes, experienced this kind of thinking. Perhaps it happened formally, with a teacher, mentor, colleague, rabbi, or the like. Or maybe it occurred on the personal plane, in partnership with a loved one, friend, parent, or child. Reading Callardâs book, I thought back to some of my own Socratic experiences. I was struck by the fact that I could remember so many of them; even years later, they stood out as remarkable. When was the last time I had that kind of conversation, and with whom? Thatâs a question potent enough to make you change how you spend your time. Almost without exception, the people with whom Iâve Socratically conversed are the most important in my life; I donât talk with them often enough.
Many of the Socratic conversations I can remember were punctual eventsâhourlong talks in an office, say, or on a walk. Others unspooled over days, weeks, or longer. In every case, however, they were possible only because certain social arrangements had brought me and my interlocutor together under the right kinds of conditions. One of Callardâs points is that good Socratic thinking requires an egalitarian contextâone in which two people can talk openly, frankly, mind to mind. Thereâs a very real sense in which âfree speech is achieved neither by debate nor by persuasion,â she writes; you speak most freely when you can describe your deepest concerns to someone whose opinion you value, and who is really listening to you and speaking honestly in reply. Post all you want onlineâeven on the new, âuncensoredâ version of Facebookâand you probably wonât find that kind of heightened freedom. One implication of this view is that itâs possible to create a society in which debate thrives, but thinking does not.
A common objection to Socrates is that heâs too negative: he just asks you questions until youâre forced to admit to confusion or ignorance. Another is that heâs too intellectual: he takes a concept that should be obvious and intuitive and, through interrogation, overcomplicates it. Why not just live your life, instead of talking about it endlessly? Callard argues that this sort of anti-intellectual skepticism is only possible if you underestimate the value of Socratic thinking. She recalls a student who was so taken by a sentence of Aristotleâs that he proposed getting it tattooed on his arm. âWhy donât you try to understand it instead?â she tells him. âThatâs like tattooing it onto your soul.â A âSocratizing move,â she writes, is to figure out, in the course of conversation, that âA is the real Bâ; the discovery that âunderstanding is the real tattooâ typifies how Socratic dialogue âscrapes the dust and cobwebs off of an ordinary or everyday concept and reveals it to be something higher, more transcendent, more demanding, and often more real than we had thought.â (âOne of lifeâs hardest jobs,â Saul Bellow wrote, in his novel âHerzog,â is âto make a quick understanding slow.â)
The protagonist of âOpen Socratesâ lived more than two thousand years ago, and wore no shoes. It isnât, strictly speaking, a book about technology. But it is about process and method, and so we can ask whether the technologies we use today, in the course of thinking, aid us or distract us. Clearly, there is value in discovering new opinions and learning new facts; in explaining your views to strangers (or, for that matter, to an A.I.); and in questioning received wisdom. The technologies in which weâre immersed facilitate all of this. But they donât, in themselves, exhaust the work of thinking. Provocations furnished by an algorithm can only take you so far; thoughts shared one way, through the narrow apertures afforded by âdebate,â only count for so much.
This is because, oddly, itâs not what you think that matters. If you live on a desert island, Callard writes, then you might tell yourself that you have an independent cast of mind; you might boast of knowing what you think. On the island, youâre free to question everything and decide on your own answers. But what good is isolated certainty, ultimately? âIt is only when our independence is the product of a shared agreement about how to live that it counts as a form of freedom,â Callard argues. Thinking, in other words, must be social, because living is social. There are different kinds of social life; some strengthen our thinking more than others. Could it really be true that, outside of the scientific method, weâve invented no better technology for the generation of durable, shared agreement than deep, open, one-on-one conversation? It might be worth arranging a walk with a friend, to talk it over. âŚ
Source link